Do the rights of patients in healthcare trump everyone else's rights? |
Note: This excerpt is the
second in a series of essays on conscience in healthcare, by Jonathan Imbody, Vice
President for Government Relations of the Christian
Medical Association and Director of Freedom2Care. For other essays, click "ConscienceEssay" under Topics, at left.
In a New England Journal of Medicine piece entitled, "Physicians, Not Conscripts — Conscientious Objection in Health Care,"[i] Obamacare architect Dr. Emanuel Ezekiel and professor Ronit Stahl assert that the "rights of
patients" in healthcare trump everyone else's rights. But why? On what
basis? It's one thing to expect physicians to do everything possible to advance healing for patients. It's quite another to insist that whatever the patient wants, the patient gets--so the physician must provide it at risk of his or her career.
Whenever one group gets its way regardless of the impact on
others, that is not autonomy; that is tyranny.
As I wrote in my book, Faith Steps,
"The trouble with adopting autonomy as the only guiding 'rule' is that while compromise and avoidance may work for a while, conflicting worldviews inevitably produce an irreconcilable conflict. By definition, autonomy is utterly incapable of resolving an irreconcilable conflict. The rule of autonomy can only avoid judgment; it cannot make a judgment."[ii]
Autonomy (literally, self-law) is by definition impossible
whenever one depends on others. The fact that patients depend on physicians, on
payers and a myriad of other health entities by definition means that patients
are not and cannot be autonomous. So a medical ethic that insists on pure
patient autonomy is at best unworkable and at worst disruptive to the entire
healthcare system.
To achieve health goals, no one party can assert autonomy in
our complex and interwoven healthcare system. Doctors can't do whatever they
want and patients can't get whatever they want. Payers can't exist without
premiums or government funds and the accountability and regulation that comes
with both.
Success in our healthcare system requires cooperation--not domination. |
Success in our healthcare system requires cooperation--not domination. And
cooperation requires addressing the goals and needs of each party.
In the authors' view, however, in cases of conflict, patients
get what they want regardless of the conscience concerns of health
professionals or institutions:
"Making the patient paramount means offering and providing accepted medical interventions in accordance with patients’ reasoned decisions."[iii]
Suddenly a patient's "reasoned decision" replaces
medical judgment and nullifies longstanding principles of medicine that include
conscience protection.
The authors deploy the phrase "reasoned decisions"
in an effort to paint any opponents as by definition unreasonable; they argue with a patient's "reasoned decision."
The authors never specify, of course, what qualifies as a "reasoned
decision." One can only imagine what a patient's "reasoned
decision" might sound like in practice:
"Oh don't worry, doctor--I saw
a commercial about this drug and researched it on the Internet."
"Well, I'm saying that my back still hurts and I want another prescription
of Oxycontin now."
"I know I'm only 14¸but my
college boyfriend says I need to start taking the Pill. And don't tell my
Mom."
Besides asserting a patient oligarchy, the authors also
attempt to conflate asserted rights
of patients with the well-being of
patients. Yet asserted rights and well-being are not always compatible.
What happens, for example, when a patient asserts a right to
a prescription or a medical procedure that medical evidence and/or professional
judgment indicates would not advance the patient's well-being? Isn't that
exactly the point at which we want qualified medical professionals to intervene,
to prevent harm to the patient?
Choosing a healing profession does not mandate
killing
Two patients. |
The question of harm to the patient comes into focus in
the issue of abortion. Many Ob-Gyn physicians see their task as tending to two
patients—the mother and her developing baby. Most women visiting an Ob-Gyn for
prenatal care clearly share this view.
Yet Emanuel and Stahl apparently see no contradiction in
compelling Ob-Gyn physicians, who chose a profession of healing, to participate in killing
an unborn child through abortion. As to the well-being of the patient who is also
a mother, the authors mention no consideration of abortion's potential for
emotional or physical harm as a legitimate reason for a physician to counsel a
patient against abortion.[iv]
Not only do the authors fail to see abortion as
antithetical to a healing profession and a blatant violation of the Hippocratic
oath; they go so far as to contend that abortion is "medically not
controversial."[v] They frame abortion not
as antithetical to but as integral to patient care. Therefore, they reason,
ending the life of a pregnant patient's developing baby constitutes
"patient care," and abortion on demand thus trumps a physician's
conscience freedom.
The patient wants an abortion, the patient gets an
abortion, end of story. Any physician who disagrees does not deserve to remain
in the profession:
"Health care professionals who are unwilling to accept these limits have two choices: select an area of medicine, such as radiology, that will not put them in situations that conflict with their personal morality or, if there is no such area, leave the profession."[vi]
Of course, erecting such barriers to everyone who does not
share the ideological persuasions of the authors would eliminate from medicine tens
of thousands of physicians at a time of critical shortage of physicians. The
result would be a catastrophic loss of healthcare for tens of millions of
patients.
Ejecting conscientious objectors from medicine would cause a catastrophic loss of healthcare for tens of millions of patients. |
[i] "Physicians, Not Conscripts — Conscientious Objection in Health Care," Ronit Y. Stahl, Ph.D. and Ezekiel J. Emanuel, M.D., Ph.D., New England Journal of Medicine 376;14, April 6, 2017.
[ii] Jonathan Imbody, Faith Steps: Moving toward God through personal choice and public policy, Washington, DC: Logion Publishing, Second Edition, 2016, p. 26. Available at http://tinyurl.com/FaithSteps2.
[ii] Jonathan Imbody, Faith Steps: Moving toward God through personal choice and public policy, Washington, DC: Logion Publishing, Second Edition, 2016, p. 26. Available at http://tinyurl.com/FaithSteps2.
[iii] "Physicians, Not Conscripts —
Conscientious Objection in Health Care," Ronit Y. Stahl, Ph.D. and Ezekiel
J. Emanuel, M.D., Ph.D., New England Journal of Medicine 376;14, April 6, 2017.,
p. 1383.
[iv] For a listing of selected abortion sequelae
research publications, see http://afterabortion.org/2011/abortion-risks-a-list-of-major-psychological-complications-related-to-abortion/.
[v]
Stahl and Emanuel. p. 1380.
[vi]
Ibid. p. 1383.
No comments:
Post a Comment